欢迎访问本站。
The Interpretation of Dreams Chapter 1 - E. The Psychological Peculiarities of Dreams Psychology
CHAPTER 1, Section F
F. The Ethical Sense in Dreams
For reasons which will be intelligible only after a consideration of my own
investigations of dreams, I have isolated from the psychology of the dream the
subsidiary problem as to whether and to what extent the moral dispositions and
feelings of waking life extend into dream-life. The same contradictions which we
were surprised to observe in the descriptions by various authors of all the
other psychic activities will surprise us again here. Some writers flatly assert
that dreams know nothing of moral obligations; others as decidedly declare that
the moral nature of man persists even in his dream-life.
Our ordinary experience of dreams seems to confirm beyond all doubt the
correctness of the first assertion. Jessen says (p. 553): "Nor does one become
better or more virtuous during sleep; on the contrary, it seems that conscience
is silent in our dreams, inasmuch as one feels no compassion and can commit the
worst crimes, such as theft, murder, and homicide, with perfect indifference and
without subsequent remorse."
Radestock (p. 146) says: "It is to be noted that in dreams associations are
effected and ideas combined without being in any way influenced by reflection,
reason, aesthetic taste, and moral judgment; the judgment is extremely weak, and
ethical indifference reigns supreme."
Volkelt (p. 23) expresses himself as follows: "As every one knows, dreams are
especially unbridled in sexual matters. Just as the dreamer himself is shameless
in the extreme, and wholly lacking in moral feeling and judgment, so likewise
does he see others, even the most respected persons, doing things which, even in
his thoughts, he would blush to associate with them in his waking state."
Utterances like those of Schopenhauer, that in dreams every man acts and talks
in complete accordance with his character, are in sharpest contradiction to
those mentioned above. R. Ph. Fischer * maintains that the subjective feelings
and desires, or affects and passions, manifest themselves in the wilfulness of
the dream-life, and that the moral characteristics of a man are mirrored in his
dreams.
* Grundzuge des Systems der Anthropologie. Erlangen, 1850 (quoted by Spitta).
Haffner says (p. 25): "With rare exceptions... a virtuous man will be virtuous
also in his dreams; he will resist temptation, and show no sympathy for hatred,
envy, anger, and all other vices; whereas the sinful man will, as a rule,
encounter in his dreams the images which he has before him in the waking state."
Scholz (p. 36): "In dreams there is truth; despite all camouflage of nobility or
degradation, we recognize our own true selves.... The honest man does not commit
a dishonouring crime even in his dreams, or, if he does, he is appalled by it as
by something foreign to his nature. The Roman emperor who ordered one of his
subjects to be executed because he dreamed that he had cut off the emperor's
head was not far wrong in justifying his action on the ground that he who has
such dreams must have similar thoughts while awake. Significantly enough, we say
of things that find no place even in our intimate thoughts: 'I would never even
dream of such a thing.'"
Plato, on the other hand, considers that they are the best men who only dream
the things which other men do.
Plaff, * varying a familiar proverb, says: "Tell me your dreams for a time and I
will tell you what you are within."
* Das Traumleben und seine Deutung, 1868 (cited by Spitta, p. 192).
The little essay of Hildebrandt's from which I have already taken so many
quotations (the best-expressed and most suggestive contribution to the
literature of the dream-problem which I have hitherto discovered), takes for its
central theme the problem of morality in dreams. For Hildebrandt, too, it is an
established rule that the purer the life, the purer the dream; the impurer the
life, the impurer the dream.
The moral nature of man persists even in dreams. "But while we are not offended
or made suspicious by an arithmetical error, no matter how obvious, by a
reversal of scientific fact, no matter how romantic, or by an anachronism, no
matter how ridiculous, we nevertheless do not lose sight of the difference
between good and evil, right and wrong, virtue and vice. No matter how much of
that which accompanies us during the day may vanish in our hours of sleep,
Kant's categorical imperative dogs our steps as an inseparable companion, of
whom we cannot rid ourselves even in our slumber.... This can be explained only
by the fact that the fundamental element of human nature, the moral essence, is
too firmly fixed to be subjected to the kaleidoscopic shaking-up to which
phantasy, reason, memory, and other faculties of the same order succumb in our
dreams" (p. 45, etc.).
In the further discussion of the subject we find in both these groups of authors
remarkable evasions and inconsequences. Strictly speaking, all interest in
immoral dreams should be at an end for those who assert that the moral
personality of the individual falls to pieces in his dreams. They could as
coolly reject all attempts to hold the dreamer responsible for his dreams, or to
infer from the immorality of his dreams that there is an immoral strain in his
nature, as they have rejected the apparently analogous attempt to prove from the
absurdity of his dreams the worthlessness of his intellectual life in the waking
state. The others, according to whom the categorical imperative extends even
into the dream, ought to accept in toto the notion of full responsibility for
immoral dreams; and we can only hope that their own reprehensible dreams do not
lead them to abandon their otherwise firm belief in their own moral worth.
As a matter of fact, however, it would seem that although no one is positively
certain just how good or how bad he is, he can hardly deny that he can recollect
immoral dreams of his own. That there are such dreams no one denies; the only
question is: how do they originate? So that, in spite of their conflicting
judgments of dream-morality, both groups of authors are at pains to explain the
genesis of the immoral dream; and here a new conflict arises, as to whether its
origin is to be sought in the normal functions of the psychic life, or in the
somatically conditioned encroachments upon this life. The nature of the facts
compels both those who argue for and those who argue against moral
responsibility in dream-life to agree in recognizing a special psychic source
for the immorality of dreams.
Those who maintain that morality continues to function in our dream-life
nevertheless refrain from assuming full responsibility for their dreams. Haffner
says (p. 24): "We are not responsible for our dreams, because that basis which
alone gives our life truth and reality is withdrawn from our thoughts and our
will. Hence the wishes and actions of our dreams cannot be virtuous or sinful."
Yet the dreamer is responsible for the sinful dream in so far as indirectly he
brings it about. Thus, as in waking life, it is his duty, just before going to
sleep, morally to cleanse his mind.
The analysis of this admixture of denial and recognition of responsibility for
the moral content of dreams is carried much further by Hildebrandt. After
arguing that the dramatic method of representation characteristic of dreams, the
condensation of the most complicated processes of reflection into the briefest
periods of time, and the debasement and confusion of the imaginative elements of
dreams, which even he admits must be allowed for in respect of the immoral
appearance of dreams, he nevertheless confesses that there are the most serious
objections to flatly denying all responsibility for the lapses and offenses of
which we are guilty in our dreams.
(p. 49): "If we wish to repudiate very decisively any sort of unjust accusation,
and especially one which has reference to our intentions and convictions, we use
the expression: 'We should never have dreamt of such a thing.' By this, it is
true, we mean on the one hand that we consider the region of dreams the last and
remotest place in which we could be held responsible for our thoughts, because
there these thoughts are so loosely and incoherently connected with our real
being that we can, after all, hardly regard them as our own; but inasmuch as we
feel impelled expressly to deny the existence of such thoughts even in this
region, we are at the same time indirectly admitting that our justification
would not be complete unless it extended even thus far. And I believe that here,
although unconsciously, we are speaking the language of truth."
(p. 52): "No dream-action can be imagined whose first beginnings have not in
some shape already passed through the mind during our waking hours, in the form
of wish, desire, or impulse." Concerning this original impulse we must say: The
dream has not discovered it- it has only imitated and extended it; it has only
elaborated into dramatic form a scrap of historical material which it found
already existing within us; it brings to our mind the words of the Apostle that
he who hates his brother is a murderer. And though, after we wake, being
conscious of our moral strength, we may smile at the whole widely elaborated
structure of the depraved dream, yet the original material out of which we
formed it cannot be laughed away. One feels responsible for the transgressions
of one's dreaming self; not for the whole sum of them, but yet for a certain
percentage. "In short, if in this sense, which can hardly be impugned, we
understand the words of Christ, that out of the heart come evil thoughts, then
we can hardly help being convinced that every sin committed in our dreams brings
with it at least a vague minimum of guilt."
Thus Hildebrandt finds the source of the immorality of dreams in the germs and
hints of evil impulses which pass through our minds during the day as mental
temptations, and he does not hesitate to include these immoral elements in the
ethical evaluation of the personality. These same thoughts, and the same
evaluation of these thoughts, have, as we know, caused devout and holy men of
all ages to lament that they were wicked sinners. *
* It is not uninteresting to consider the attitude of the Inquisition to this
problem. In the Tractatus de Officio sanctissimae Inquisitionis of Thomas Carena
(Lyons edit., 1659) one finds the following passage: "Should anyone utter
heresies in his dreams, the inquisitors shall consider this a reason for
investigating his conduct in life, for that is wont to return in sleep which
occupies a man during the day" (Dr. Ehniger, St. Urban, Switzerland).
The general occurrence of these contrasting thoughts in the majority of men, and
even in other regions than the ethical, is of course established beyond a doubt.
They have sometimes been judged in a less serious spirit. Spitta quotes a
relevant passage from A. Zeller (Article "Irre," in the Allgemeine Encyklopadie
der Wissenschaften, Ersch and Gruber, p. 144): "An intellect is rarely so
happily organized as to be in full command of itself at all times and seasons,
and never to be disturbed in the lucid and constant processes of thought by
ideas not merely unessential, but absolutely grotesque and nonsensical; indeed,
the greatest thinkers have had cause to complain of this dream-like, tormenting
and distressing rabble of ideas, which disturbs their profoundest contemplations
and their most pious and earnest meditations."
A clearer light is thrown on the psychological meaning of these contrasting
thoughts by a further observation of Hildebrandt's, to the effect that dreams
permit us an occasional glimpse of the deepest and innermost recesses of our
being, which are generally closed to us in our waking state (p. 55). A
recognition of this fact is betrayed by Kant in his Anthropology, when he states
that our dreams may perhaps be intended to reveal to us not what we are but what
we might have been if we had had another upbringing; and by Radestock (p. 84),
who suggests that dreams disclose to us what we do not wish to admit to
ourselves, and that we therefore unjustly condemn them as lying and deceptive.
J. E. Erdmann asserts: "A dream has never told me what I ought to think of a
person, but, to my great surprise, a dream has more than once taught me what I
do really think of him and feel about him." And J. H. Fichte expresses himself
in a like manner: "The character of our dreams gives a far truer reflection of
our general disposition than anything that we can learn by self-observation in
the waking state." Such remarks as this of Benini's call our attention to the
fact that the emergence of impulses which are foreign to our ethical
consciousness is merely analogous to the manner, already familiar to us, in
which the dream disposes of other representative material: "Certe nostre
inclinazioni che si credevano soffocate e spente da un pezzo, si ridestano;
passioni vecchie e sepolte revivono; cose e persone a cui non pensiamo mai, ci
vengono dinanzi" (p. 149). Volkelt expresses himself in a similar fashion: "Even
ideas which have entered into our consciousness almost unnoticed, and which,
perhaps, it has never before called out of oblivion, often announce their
presence in the mind through a dream" (p 105). Finally, we may remember that
according to Schleiermacher the state of falling asleep is accompanied by the
appearance of undesired imaginings.
We may include in such "undesired imaginings" the whole of that imaginative
material the occurrence of which surprises us in immoral as well as in absurd
dreams. The only important difference consists in the fact that the undesired
imaginings in the moral sphere are in opposition to our usual feelings, whereas
the others merely appear strange to us. So far nothing has been done to enable
us to reconcile this difference by a profounder understanding. But what is the
significance of the emergence of undesired representations in dreams? What
conclusions can the psychology of the waking and dreaming mind draw from these
nocturnal manifestations of contrasting ethical impulses? Here we find a fresh
diversity of opinion, and also a different grouping of the authors who have
treated of the subject. The line of thought followed by Hildebrandt, and by
others who share his fundamental opinion, cannot be continued otherwise than by
ascribing to the immoral impulses, even in the waking state, a latent vitality,
which is indeed inhibited from proceeding to action, and by asserting that
during sleep something falls away from us which, having the effect of an
inhibition, has kept us from becoming aware of the existence of such impulses.
Dreams therefore, reveal the true, if not the whole, nature of the dreamer, and
are one means of making the hidden life of the psyche accessible to our
understanding. It is only on such hypotheses that Hildebrandt can attribute to
the dream the role of a monitor who calls our attention to the secret mischief
in the soul, just as, according to the physicians, it may announce a hitherto
unobserved physical disorder. Spitta, too, must be influenced by this conception
when he refers, for example, to the stream of excitations which flow in upon the
psyche during puberty, and consoles the dreamer by assuring him that he has done
all that is in his power to do if he has led a strictly virtuous life during his
waking state, if he has made an effort to suppress the sinful thoughts as often
as they arise, and has kept them from maturing and turning into action.
According to this conception, we might designate as "undesired imaginings" those
that are suppressed during the day, and we must recognize in their emergence a
genuine psychic phenomenon.
According to certain other authors, we have no right to draw this last
inference. For Jessen (p. 360) the undesired ideas and images, in the dream as
in the waking state, and also in the delirium of fever, etc., possess "the
character of a voluntary activity laid to rest, and of a procession, to some
extent mechanical, of images and ideas evoked by inner impulses." An immoral
dream proves nothing in respect of the psychic life of the dreamer except that
he has somehow become cognizant of the imaginative content in question; it is
certainly no proof of a psychic impulse of his own mind. Another writer, Maury,
makes us wonder whether he, too, does not ascribe to the dream-state the power
of dividing the psychic activity into its components, instead of aimlessly
destroying it. He speaks as follows of dreams in which one oversteps the bounds
of morality: "Ce sont nos penchants qui parlent et qui nous font agir, sans que
la conscience nous retienne, bien que parfois elle nous avertisse. J'ai mes
defauts et mes penchants vicieux; a l'etat de veille, je tache de lutter contre
eux, et il m'arrive assez souvent de n'y pas succomber. Mais dans mes songes j'y
succombe toujours, ou pour mieux dire j'agis par leur impulsion, sans crainte et
sans remords.... Evidemment les visions qui se deroulent devant ma pensee, et
qui constituent le reve, me sont suggerees par les incitations que je ressens et
que ma volonte absente ne cherche pas a refouler."- * Le Sommeil (p. 113).
* Our tendencies speak and make us act, without being restrained by our
conscience, although it sometimes warns us. I have my faults and vicious
tendencies; awake I try to fight against them, and often enough I do not succumb
to them. But in my dreams I always succumb, or, rather, I act at their
direction, without fear or remorse.... Evidently, the visions which unfold in my
thoughts, and which constitute the dream, are suggested by the stimuli which I
feel and which my absent will does not try to repel.
If one believed in the power of the dream to reveal an actually existing, but
suppressed or concealed, immoral disposition of the dreamer, one could not
express one's opinion more emphatically than in the words of Maury (p. 115): "En
reve l'homme se revele donc tout entier a soi-meme dans sa nudite et sa misere
natives. Des qu'il suspend l'exercise de sa volonte, il devient le jouet de
toutes les passions contre lesquelles, a l'etat de veille, la conscience, le
sentiment d'honneur, la crainte nous defendent." * In another place makes the
striking assertion (p. 462): "Dans le reve, c'est surtout l'homme instinctif que
se revele.... L'homme revient pour ainsi dire l'etat de nature quand il reve;
mais moins les idees acquises ont penetre dans son esprit, plus 'les penchants
en desaccord' avec elles conservent encore sur lui d'influence dans le rive."
*(2) He then mentions, as an example, that his own dreams often reveal him as a
victim of just those superstitions which he has most vigorously attacked in his
writings.
* In a dream, a man is totally revealed to himself in his naked and wretched
state. As he suspends the exercise of his will, he becomes the toy of all the
passions from which, when awake, our conscience, horror, and fear defend us.
*(2) In a dream, it is above all the instinctive man who is revealed.... Man
returns, so to speak, to the natural state when he dreams; but the less acquired
ideas have penetrated into his mind, the more his "tendencies to disagreement"
with them keep their hold on him in his dreams.
The value of all these acute observations is, however, impaired in Maury's case,
because he refuses to recognize in the phenomena which he has so accurately
observed anything more than a proof of the automatisme psychologique which in
his own opinion dominates the dream-life. He conceives this automatism as the
complete opposite of psychic activity.
A passage in Stricker's Studien uber das Bewusstsein reads: "Dreams do not
consist purely and simply of delusions; for example, if one is afraid of robbers
in a dream, the robbers indeed are imaginary, but the fear is real." Our
attention is here called to the fact that the affective development of a dream
does not admit of the judgment which one bestows upon the rest of the
dream-content, and the problem then arises: What part of the psychic processes
in a dream may be real? That is to say, what part of them may claim to be
enrolled among the psychic processes of the waking state?
The Interpretation of Dreams
Chapter 1 - G. Dream-Theories and the Function of the Dream
感谢您访问本站。